The Essays of Arthur Schopenhauer; the Art of Controversy
140 pages
English

The Essays of Arthur Schopenhauer; the Art of Controversy

-

Le téléchargement nécessite un accès à la bibliothèque YouScribe
Tout savoir sur nos offres
140 pages
English
Le téléchargement nécessite un accès à la bibliothèque YouScribe
Tout savoir sur nos offres

Description

The Project Gutenberg eBook, The Essays of Arthur Schopenhauer; The Art of Controversy, by Arthur Schopenhauer,Translated by T. Bailey SaundersThis eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it,give it away or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included with this eBook or online atwww.gutenberg.netTitle: The Essays of Arthur Schopenhauer; The Art of ControversyAuthor: Arthur SchopenhauerRelease Date: January 17, 2004 [eBook #10731]Language: English***START OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK THE ESSAYS OF ARTHUR SCHOPENHAUER; THE ART OFCONTROVERSY***E-text prepared by Juliet Sutherland, Josephine Paolucci, and the Project Gutenberg Online Distributed ProofreadingTeamTHE ESSAYS OF ARTHUR SCHOPENHAUER: THE ART OF CONTROVERSYTRANSLATED BYT. BAILEY SAUNDERS, M.A.CONTENTS.THE ART OF CONTROVERSY— 1. PRELIMINARY: LOGIC AND DIALECTIC 2. THE BASIS OF ALL DIALECTIC 3. STRATAGEMS ON THE COMPARATIVEPLACE OF INTEREST AND BEAUTY IN WORKS OF ART PSYCHOLOGICAL OBSERVATIONS ON THE WISDOM OF LIFE: APHORISMS GENIUS AND VIRTUETRANSLATOR'S PREFACE.The volume now before the reader is a tardy addition to a series in which I have endeavoured to present Schopenhauer'sminor writings in an adequate form.Its contents are drawn entirely from his posthumous papers. A selection of them was given to the world some three of fouryears after his death by his friend and literary executor, Julius ...

Informations

Publié par
Publié le 08 décembre 2010
Nombre de lectures 49
Langue English

Extrait

The Project Gutenberg eBook, The Essays ofArthur Schopenhauer; The Art of Controversy, byArthur Schopenhauer, Translated by T. BaileySaundersThis eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere atno cost and with almost no restrictions whatsoever.You may copy it, give it away or re-use it under theterms of the Project Gutenberg License includedwith this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.netTitle: The Essays of Arthur Schopenhauer; The Artof ControversyAuthor: Arthur SchopenhauerRelease Date: January 17, 2004 [eBook #10731]Language: English***START OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERGEBOOK THE ESSAYS OF ARTHURSCHOPENHAUER; THE ART OFCONTROVERSY***
E-text prepared by Juliet Sutherland, JosephinePaolucci, and the Project Gutenberg OnlineDistributed Proofreading TeamTHE ESSAYS OF ARTHURSCHOPENHAUER: THE ART OFCONTROVERSYTRANSLATED BYT. BAILEY SAUNDERS, M.A.CONTENTS.THE ART OF CONTROVERSY— 1.PRELIMINARY: LOGIC AND DIALECTIC 2. THEBASIS OF ALL DIALECTIC 3. STRATAGEMS ONTHE COMPARATIVE PLACE OF INTEREST AND
BEAUTY IN WORKS OF ART PSYCHOLOGICALOBSERVATIONS ON THE WISDOMAPHORISMS GENIUS AND VIRTUE OF LIFE:
TRANSLATOR'S PREFACE.The volume now before the reader is a tardyaddition to a series in which I have endeavoured topresent Schopenhauer's minor writings in anadequate form.Its contents are drawn entirely from hisposthumous papers. A selection of them was givento the world some three of four years after hisdeath by his friend and literary executor, JuliusFrauenstädt, who for this and other offices of piety,has received less recognition than he deserves.The papers then published have recently beenissued afresh, with considerable additions andcorrections, by Dr. Eduard Grisebach, who is alsoentitled to gratitude for the care with which he hasfollowed the text of the manuscripts, now in theRoyal Library at Berlin, and for having drawnattention—although in terms that are unnecessarilysevere—to a number of faults and failings on thepart of the previous editor.The fact that all Schopenhauer's works, togetherwith a volume of his correspondence, may now beobtained in a certain cheap collection of the bestnational and foreign literature displayed in almostevery bookshop in Germany, is sufficient evidencethat in his own country the writer's popularity is stillvery great; nor does the demand for translationsindicate that his fame has at all diminished abroad.The favour with which the new edition of his
posthumous papers has been received inducesme, therefore, to resume a task which I thought,five years ago, that I had finally completed; and itis my intention to bring out one more volume,selected partly from these papers and partly fromhis Parerga.A small part of the essay on The Art ofControversy was published in Schopenhauer'slifetime, in the chapter of the Parerga headed ZurLogik und Dialektik. The intelligent reader willdiscover that a good deal of its contents is of anironical character. As regards the last three essaysI must observe that I have omitted such passagesas appear to be no longer of any general interestor otherwise unsuitable. I must also confess tohaving taken one or two liberties with the titles, inorder that they may the more effectively fulfil thepurpose for which titles exist. In other respects Ihave adhered to the original with the kind of fidelitywhich aims at producing an impression as nearlyas possible similar to that produced by the original.T.B.S.February, 1896
THE ART OF CONTROVERSY.PRELIMINARY: LOGIC AND DIALECTIC.By the ancients, Logic and Dialectic were used assynonymous terms; although [Greek: logizesthai],"to think over, to consider, to calculate," and[Greek: dialegesthai], "to converse," are two verydifferent things.The name Dialectic was, as we are informed byDiogenes Laertius, first used by Plato; and in thePhaedrus, Sophist, Republic, bk. vii., andelsewhere, we find that by Dialectic he means theregular employment of the reason, and skill in thepractice of it. Aristotle also uses the word in thissense; but, according to Laurentius Valla, he wasthe first to use Logic too in a similar way.[1]Dialectic, therefore, seems to be an older wordthan Logic. Cicero and Quintilian use the words inthe same general signification.[2][Footnote 1: He speaks of [Greek: dyscherelailogicai], that is, "difficult points," [Greek: protasislogicae aporia logicae]][Footnote 2: Cic. in Lucullo: Dialecticam inventamesse, veri et falsi quasi disceptatricem. Topica, c.2: Stoici enim judicandi vias diligenter persecutisunt, ea scientia, quam Dialecticen appellant.Quint., lib. ii., 12: Itaque haec pars dialecticae, siveillam disputatricem dicere malimus; and with him
this latter word appears to be the Latin equivalentfor Dialectic. (So far according to "Petri Ramidialectica, Audomari Talaei praelectionibusillustrata." 1569.)]This use of the words and synonymous termslasted through the Middle Ages into modern times;in fact, until the present day. But more recently,and in particular by Kant, Dialectic has often beenemployed in a bad sense, as meaning "the art ofsophistical controversy"; and hence Logic has beenpreferred, as of the two the more innocentdesignation. Nevertheless, both originally meantthe same thing; and in the last few years they haveagain been recognised as synonymous.It is a pity that the words have thus been usedfrom of old, and that I am not quite at liberty todistinguish their meanings. Otherwise, I shouldhave preferred to define Logic (from [Greek:logos], "word" and "reason," which are inseparable)as "the science of the laws of thought, that is, ofthe method of reason"; and Dialectic (from [Greek:dialegesthai], "to converse"—and everyconversation communicates either facts oropinions, that is to say, it is historical ordeliberative) as "the art of disputation," in themodern sense of the word. It it clear, then, thatLogic deals with a subject of a purely à prioricharacter, separable in definition from experience,namely, the laws of thought, the process of reasonor the [Greek: logos], the laws, that is, whichreason follows when it is left to itself and nothindered, as in the case of solitary thought on the
part of a rational being who is in no way misled.Dialectic, on the other hand, would treat of theintercourse between two rational beings who,because they are rational, ought to think incommon, but who, as soon as they cease to agreelike two clocks keeping exactly the same time,create a disputation, or intellectual contest.Regarded as purely rational beings, the individualswould, I say, necessarily be in agreement, andtheir variation springs from the difference essentialto individuality; in other words, it is drawn fromexperience.Logic, therefore, as the science of thought, or thescience of the process of pure reason, should becapable of being constructed à priori. Dialectic, forthe most part, can be constructed only à posteriori;that is to say, we may learn its rules by anexperiential knowledge of the disturbance whichpure thought suffers through the difference ofindividuality manifested in the intercourse betweentwo rational beings, and also by acquaintance withthe means which disputants adopt in order to makegood against one another their own individualthought, and to show that it is pure and objective.For human nature is such that if A. and B. areengaged in thinking in common, and arecommunicating their opinions to one another onany subject, so long as it is not a mere fact ofhistory, and A. perceives that B.'s thoughts on oneand the same subject are not the same as his own,he does not begin by revising his own process ofthinking, so as to discover any mistake which hemay have made, but he assumes that the mistake
has occurred in B.'s. In other words, man isnaturally obstinate; and this quality in him isattended with certain results, treated of in thebranch of knowledge which I should like to callDialectic, but which, in order to avoidmisunderstanding, I shall call Controversial orEristical Dialectic. Accordingly, it is the branch ofknowledge which treats of the obstinacy natural toman. Eristic is only a harsher name for the samething.Controversial Dialectic is the art of disputing, andof disputing in such a way as to hold one's own,whether one is in the right or the wrong—per fas etnefas.[1] A man may be objectively in the right,and nevertheless in the eyes of bystanders, andsometimes in his own, he may come off worst. Forexample, I may advance a proof of someassertion, and my adversary may refute the proof,and thus appear to have refuted the assertion, forwhich there may, nevertheless, be other proofs. Inthis case, of course, my adversary and I changeplaces: he comes off best, although, as a matter offact, he is in the wrong.[Footnote 1: According to Diogenes Laertius, v.,28, Aristotle put Rhetoric and Dialectic together, asaiming at persuasion, [Greek: to pithanon]; andAnalytic and Philosophy as aiming at truth. Aristotledoes, indeed, distinguish between (1) Logic, orAnalytic, as the theory or method of arriving at trueor apodeictic conclusions; and (2) Dialectic as themethod of arriving at conclusions that are acceptedor pass current as true, [Greek: endoxa] probabilia;
conclusions in regard to which it is not taken forgranted that they are false, and also not taken forgranted that they are true in themselves, since thatis not the point. What is this but the art of being inthe right, whether one has any reason for being soor not, in other words, the art of attaining theappearance of truth, regardless of its substance?That is, then, as I put it above.Aristotle divides all conclusions into logical anddialectical, in the manner described, and then intoeristical. (3) Eristic is the method by which the formof the conclusion is correct, but the premisses, thematerials from which it is drawn, are not true, butonly appear to be true. Finally (4) Sophistic is themethod in which the form of the conclusion is false,although it seems correct. These three lastproperly belong to the art of Controversial Dialectic,as they have no objective truth in view, but only theappearance of it, and pay no regard to truth itself;that is to say, they aim at victory. Aristotle's bookon Sophistic Conclusions was edited apart from theothers, and at a later date. It was the last book ofhis Dialectic.]If the reader asks how this is, I reply that it issimply the natural baseness of human nature. Ifhuman nature were not base, but thoroughlyhonourable, we should in every debate have noother aim than the discovery of truth; we shouldnot in the least care whether the truth proved to bein favour of the opinion which we had begun byexpressing, or of the opinion of our adversary. Thatwe should regard as a matter of no moment, or, at
  • Univers Univers
  • Ebooks Ebooks
  • Livres audio Livres audio
  • Presse Presse
  • Podcasts Podcasts
  • BD BD
  • Documents Documents