Kafka, paranoic doubles and the brain: hypnagogic vs. hyper-reflexive models of disrupted self in neuropsychiatric disorders and anomalous conscious states
37 pages
English

Découvre YouScribe en t'inscrivant gratuitement

Je m'inscris

Kafka, paranoic doubles and the brain: hypnagogic vs. hyper-reflexive models of disrupted self in neuropsychiatric disorders and anomalous conscious states

-

Découvre YouScribe en t'inscrivant gratuitement

Je m'inscris
Obtenez un accès à la bibliothèque pour le consulter en ligne
En savoir plus
37 pages
English
Obtenez un accès à la bibliothèque pour le consulter en ligne
En savoir plus

Description

Kafka's writings are frequently interpreted as representing the historical period of modernism in which he was writing. Little attention has been paid, however, to the possibility that his writings may reflect neural mechanisms in the processing of self during hypnagogic (i.e., between waking and sleep) states. Kafka suffered from dream-like, hypnagogic hallucinations during a sleep-deprived state while writing. This paper discusses reasons (phenomenological and neurobiological) why the self projects an imaginary double (autoscopy) in its spontaneous hallucinations and how Kafka's writings help to elucidate the underlying cognitive and neural mechanisms. I further discuss how the proposed mechanisms may be relevant to understanding paranoid delusions in schizophrenia. Literature documents and records cognitive and neural processes of self with an intimacy that may be otherwise unavailable to neuroscience. To elucidate this approach, I contrast it with the apparently popularizing view that the symptoms of schizophrenia result from what has been called an operative (i.e., pre-reflective) hyper-reflexivity. The latter approach claims that pre-reflective self-awareness (diminished in schizophrenia) pervades all conscious experience (however, in a manner that remains unverifiable for both phenomenological and experimental methods). This contribution argues the opposite: the "self" informs our hypnagogic imagery precisely to the extent that we are not self-aware.

Informations

Publié par
Publié le 01 janvier 2010
Nombre de lectures 20
Langue English
Poids de l'ouvrage 1 Mo

Extrait

MisharaPhilosophy, Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine2010,5:13 http://www.pehmed.com/content/5/1/13
R E S E A R C HOpen Access Kafka, paranoic doubles and the brain: hypnagogic vs. hyperreflexive models of disrupted self in neuropsychiatric disorders and anomalous conscious states Aaron L Mishara
Abstract Kafkas writings are frequently interpreted as representing the historical period of modernism in which he was writ ing. Little attention has been paid, however, to the possibility that his writings may reflect neural mechanisms in the processing of self during hypnagogic (i.e., between waking and sleep) states. Kafka suffered from dreamlike, hypnagogic hallucinations during a sleepdeprived state while writing. This paper discusses reasons (phenomenolo gical and neurobiological) why the self projects an imaginary double (autoscopy) in its spontaneous hallucinations and how Kafkas writings help to elucidate the underlying cognitive and neural mechanisms. I further discuss how the proposed mechanisms may be relevant to understanding paranoid delusions in schizophrenia. Literature docu ments and records cognitive and neural processes of self with an intimacy that may be otherwise unavailable to neuroscience. To elucidate this approach, I contrast it with the apparently popularizing view that the symptoms of schizophrenia result from what has been called an operative (i.e., prereflective) hyperreflexivity. The latter approach claims that prereflective selfawareness (diminished in schizophrenia) pervades all conscious experience (however, in a manner that remains unverifiable for both phenomenological and experimental methods). This con tribution argues the opposite: theselfinforms our hypnagogic imagery precisely to the extent that we are not selfaware.
i Background: The Natural vs. Human Sciences Cognitive and clinical neuroscience face very real pro blems about the nature of the human self, how we define and studyself,and treat individuals when the mind, or brain, becomes so disordered that the experi ence of self becomes disrupted.Cognitive neurosciencecontains the terms,mindandbrain,respectively. These terms remain imprecise due to a fundamental ambiguity that we are both minds, i.e.,beinga self (so called firstperson experience), and brains or bodies, i.e., havinga self (thirdperson perspective). The experienced body (and implicated neural pathways) is comprised by both a motoricbody (proprioceptive bodyschema), the I(as agent), and perceptualbody (exteroceptive body image), the socialme,united provisionally andfragilely
Correspondence: Aaron.Mishara@yale.edu Department of Psychiatry, Clinical Neuroscience Research Unit, Yale University School of Medicine, New Haven, CT 06519, USA
by an interoceptive body (theminenessof this rela tionship).Minenessis disrupted in hallucinations of a double orDoppelgänger. The verbal descriptorsI,me,andmine,however, are only approximations of the underlying neural processes [13]. We are generally equipped with commonsense folkpsychological views about self and how we experience other selves, which help us get by in everyday situations. Nevertheless, the self has turned out to be exceptionally difficult to define, operationalize and study in neuroscience and related disciplines. Many researchers in the fields of cognitive science/neuroscience refer to the ability to recognize self in the mirror, or make judgments involving oneself as evidence of self, but this is onesided. Much of the self awareness literature confuses mediated selfreference of higher order cognition withbeinga self. It addresses the self as object (having a self), not self as subject (being a self). By overlooking this conceptual distinction,
© 2010 Mishara; licensee BioMed Central Ltd. This is an Open Access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/2.0), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
MisharaPhilosophy, Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine2010,5:13 http://www.pehmed.com/content/5/1/13
selfreference (representational content about self or selfawareness, self as object) is confused withbeing a self(e.g., Gusnard [4]). The current exclusive focus on self as object ("selfrepresentation,rather than subject of the experience) in neuroscience has its roots in the th 19 centurydivision between the natural and human th sciences. The 19century dilemma is reflected in what Levine [5] and numerous philosophers following him, call theexplanatory gapbetween neural processes and qualia, i.e., what it isliketo experience phenomenal states. Thehuman sciences(Geisteswissenschaften, German translation of J.S. Millsmoral sciences) are based on theunderstandingof themeaningful connections
Page 2 of 37
between historical events, whereas thenatural sciences, find causalexplanationsbetween postulated natural entities [6]. Figure 1 indicates that natural sciences gen erally proceed from larger, often nebulous wholes, seek ing out explanatory relationships between eversmaller, strictly defined parts of these wholes. Explanation (e.g. causal/mechanistic, statistical/probabilistic or functional/ teleological) tries to establish relationships between sub component parts. Conversely, the historicalhuman sciences generally moveupwardsfrom partial views to everlarger contexts for understanding the matter at hand. Understanding is contextual by situating parts in greater wholes, even if these totalities are not directly available to the individual perspective but transcend or
Figure 1Methods of the natural and the humanhistorical sciences. Opposed directionality between explanation (arrow pointing to smallest circle) and understanding (arrow pointing from smallest circle), indicating the methods of the natural and humanhistorical sciences, respectively. Natural sciences proceed in terms of theclassic reductionist hierarchyfrom sociology to psychology to biology, chemistry and physics. They generally proceed from larger, rather nebulous wholes to seek out explanatory relationships between eversmaller parts of these wholes. Conversely, understanding is contextual by situating parts in evergreater wholes, even if these totalities are ultimately unavailable to the individual perspective but transcend orencompassit. Each discipline requires anabstraction, reduction to and idealization (i.e.,naming,Husserl) of theobjectsentities of its discipline (which exclude the objects of neighboring disciplines). Gray areas between disciplines indicateor interdisciplinary relationships which are often more fuzzy involving destabilizing relationships within interdisciplinary vocabulary and concepts., physis (ύsις), physicalnatural sciences;b, bios (bίος), biological sciences;ψ, psyche (ψυcή), psychologicalcognitive sciences;π, polis (πόlις), historicalcultural sciences. From Mishara [6]. Reprinted with permission from Wolters Kluwer.
MisharaPhilosophy, Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine2010,5:13 http://www.pehmed.com/content/5/1/13
encompassit (Jaspers [7]). For example, the historical human sciences themselves stand in a historical process, which is at the same time the object (as contextual totality) of their study (Gadamer [8]). Any claim to unify the natural and human sciences is burdened by seemingly insurmountable problems. These include the integration of two opposing directions of method, the effort to make the contextualunderstand ingof subjective experience somehowobjectiveand testable in the terms of natural scientific explanation, i.e., cognitive and neural processes and mechanisms. However, I make the unconventional claim (requiring justification) thatKafkas literary writing provides data about the structure of the human self. That is, it docu ments processes that are not limited to the individuals experience of self in its historical context, nor the indivi dualsautobiographicalmemory, but reflect the very structure of human self as a transformative process of selftranscendence (in symbolic dream images, a process examined further below) with its own neurobiological underpinnings, i.e., the rudiments for a discipline,lit erary neuroscience.Literature documents and records cognitive and neural processes of self with an intimacy that is otherwise unavailable to neuroscience. Such an approach is phenomenological. Founded by the mathematician turned philosopher, Edmund Husserl (18591938), phenomenology is the rigorous, methodical description of conscious experience and how the general mental structures derived from its descriptive method may be disrupted in neuropsychiatric disorders and anomalous conscious states. In its stepwise method, phenomenology approaches literary texts as providing dataabout the general structures of consciousness and ii anomalous states.By offering theoretically neutral descriptions of subjective experience (as far as this is th humanly possible), it provides a way out of the 19cen tury dilemma of studying human self aseitherobject or subject. Phenomenology proposes rather that the human dilemma is to experience oneself asbothsubject and object [9]. However, its results are provisional and may be refined by more phenomenological investigation or until tested with the experimental methods of neuroscience.
Why is the Double a Ghost? A Child? Let us start with Kafkas early story,Unhappiness(written in 1910) [10]. For our purposes, we may start with nearly any of Kafkas stories to demonstratethe same structure of doubling[1014], i.e., of the writers iii self in the protagonist,and then, a further doubling of iv the protagonist in the characters he encounters. With an approaching November evening, the narrator ofUnhappinessbegins by stating that he finds things unbearable (unerträglich). He turns away from the
Page 3 of 37
window where the street lampssuddenillumination startles him. Turning to theinteriorof his room, he finds a new goal to pursue in the depths of his own mirror(im Grund des Spiegels). The turning away from the artificial light of the streets to the dark interior of his own room and then his mirror suggest that he is turning inward to examine thedepthsof his own self. The mirror provides no answer to his loneliness and he lets out a scream in order to hear it but no one will answer. (The selfwitnessing of expression but its ulti mate ineffectiveness in reaching others are major themes further explored below); similarly, reflecting on ones owninnerself also provides no answer (as in the dis cussion ofThe Bridgebelow). The scream meets no resistance to reduce or stop it, even after it has already become silent (suggesting that the scream does nothing to diminish the pain which gives rise to it). As if in response, however, the door opens from the wall (aus der Wand heraus) and horses attached to wagons rise (sich erheben) in the air. At that moment a small ghost, a child, enters from a completely dark corridor where the lamps are still unlit. She is blinded by the room lit by dusk (Dämmerung) and covers her face. The narrator states,... in short, this visit, though I had expected it, was the one thing needful([10], p. 391). Many of the themes that concern us are announced: the protagonists loneliness, turning inward, the mirror and scream portending the sudden appearance of a dou v ble; thenarrator and his double (i.e., the childghost) experience an oversensitivity to light (photophobia); and the transformed, dreamliketwilight state (Dämmer ungzustand). All seem to reflect Kafkas own state as a writer. Curiously, the light of streetlamps and the dusk (which are not particularly intense sources of light) cause discomfort first in the narrator and then in the ghost. We know that Kafka suffered from severe, possi bly cluster headaches [15], which may, in part, contri bute to his tendency (documented below) to withdraw from excessive stimulation. The suggestion that the nar rators mental state and that of Kafka himself are closely linked is supported by the fact that both live on the vi third floor [16], p. 88The word dusk (Dämmerung) refers to the transitional light between day and night when the ghost arrives but it also refers to the narrators (writers) state of consciousness, atwilightstate(in German,Dämmerungszustand), i.e., a transitional state between waking and dreaming or sleep. Notably, the ghost is born in this moment of need, of loneliness, the searching of innerdepths in a mirror, giving rise toa cry without resonance, or echo, and which never reaches an audience. The fact that this unusual visit was some howexpectedby the narrator gives it a dreamlike quality. Even though the narrator reports bizarre, unu sual events (the ghost, the elevated horses), he does so
  • Univers Univers
  • Ebooks Ebooks
  • Livres audio Livres audio
  • Presse Presse
  • Podcasts Podcasts
  • BD BD
  • Documents Documents