Levinas and the Crisis of Humanism
169 pages
English

Vous pourrez modifier la taille du texte de cet ouvrage

Découvre YouScribe en t'inscrivant gratuitement

Je m'inscris

Levinas and the Crisis of Humanism , livre ebook

Découvre YouScribe en t'inscrivant gratuitement

Je m'inscris
Obtenez un accès à la bibliothèque pour le consulter en ligne
En savoir plus
169 pages
English

Vous pourrez modifier la taille du texte de cet ouvrage

Obtenez un accès à la bibliothèque pour le consulter en ligne
En savoir plus

Description

Levinas on educating the ethical subject


Reexamining Emmanuel Levinas's essays on Jewish education, Claire Elise Katz provides new insights into the importance of education and its potential to transform a democratic society, for Levinas's larger philosophical project. Katz examines Levinas's "Crisis of Humanism," which motivated his effort to describe a new ethical subject. Taking into account his multiple influences on social science and the humanities, and his various identities as a Jewish thinker, philosopher, and educator, Katz delves deeply into Levinas's works to understand the grounding of this ethical subject.


Preface
Acknowledgements
List of Abbreviations
Introduction
1. The Limits of the Humanities
2. Solitary Men
3. The Crisis of Humanism
4. Before Phenomenology
5. The Promise of Jewish Education
6. Teaching, Fecundity, Responsibility
7. Humanism Found
Notes
Bibliography
Index

Sujets

Informations

Publié par
Date de parution 11 décembre 2012
Nombre de lectures 3
EAN13 9780253007674
Langue English

Informations légales : prix de location à la page 0,0500€. Cette information est donnée uniquement à titre indicatif conformément à la législation en vigueur.

Extrait

LEVINAS AND THE CRISIS OF HUMANISM
CLAIRE ELISE KATZ
LEVINAS AND THE CRISIS OF HUMANISM
This book is a publication of
Indiana University Press 601 North Morton Street Bloomington, Indiana 47404-3797 USA
iupress.indiana.edu
Telephone orders 800-842-6796 Fax orders 812-855-7931
2013 by Claire Elise Katz
All rights reserved
No part of this book may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying and recording, or by any information storage and retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publisher. The Association of American University Presses Resolution on Permissions constitutes the only exception to this prohibition.
The paper used in this publication meets the minimum requirements of the American National Standard for Information Sciences-Permanence of Paper for Printed Library Materials, ANSI Z39.48-1992.
Manufactured in the United States of America
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Katz, Claire Elise, [date]
Levinas and the crisis of humanism / Claire Elise Katz.
p. cm.
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 978-0-253-00762-9 (cloth : alk. paper) - ISBN 978-0-253-00765-0 (pbk. : alk. paper) - ISBN 978-0-253-00767-4 (electronic book) 1. L vinas, Emmanuel. 2. Education-Philosophy. 3. Humanities-Philosophy. I. Title.
B2430.L484K37 2012
144-dc23
2012026292
1 2 3 4 5 18 17 16 15 14 13
To Dan, for everything and to our daughters Olivia and Evie Deuteronomy 22:3
Here I am; send me (Isaiah 6:8)
But in truth I know nothing about education except this: that the greatest and the most important difficulty known to human learning seems to lie in that area which treats how to bring up children and how to educate them.
-Michel de Montaigne, On educating children
This crippling of individuals I consider the worst evil of capitalism. Our whole educational system suffers from this evil. An exaggerated competitive attitude is inculcated into the student, who is trained to worship acquisitive success as a preparation for his future career. I am convinced there is only one way to eliminate these grave evils, namely through the establishment of a socialist economy, accompanied by an educational system which would be oriented toward social goals. In such an economy, the means of production are owned by society itself and are utilised in a planned fashion. A planned economy, which adjusts production to the needs of the community, would distribute the work to be done among all those able to work and would guarantee a livelihood to every man, woman and child. The education of the individual, in addition to promoting his own innate abilities, would attempt to develop in him a sense of responsibility for his fellow-men in place of the glorification of power and success in our present society.
-Albert Einstein, On Education (1949)
And here I am not speaking of the elite among us who were real Resistants, but of all Frenchmen who, at every hour of the night and day throughout four years, answered NO. But the very cruelty of the enemy drove us to the extremities of this condition by forcing us to ask ourselves questions that one never considers in time of peace . . . Resistance was a true democracy: for the soldier as for the commander, the same danger, the same forsakenness, the same total responsibility, the same absolute liberty within discipline. Thus, in darkness and in blood, a Republic was established, the strongest of Republics. Each of its citizens knew that he owed himself to all and that he could count only on himself alone. Each of them, in complete isolation, fulfilled his responsibility and his role in history.
-Jean-Paul Sartre, The Republic of Silence
Contents
Preface
Acknowledgments
List of Abbreviations
Introduction
1. The Limits of the Humanities
2. Solitary Men
3. The Crisis of Humanism
4. Before Phenomenology
5. The Promise of Jewish Education
6. Teaching, Fecundity, Responsibility
7. Humanism Found
Notes
Bibliography
Index
Preface
In many ways, I have been writing this book since I was an undergraduate discussing education with my grandparents when I shared Friday night dinners with them. My grandfather, z l, a retired college professor and a fan of John Dewey s philosophy of education, was a formidable interlocutor. My grandmother, with an advanced degree in library science from Columbia University, could hold her own. It was around their kitchen table that they pressed me to reflect on the college education I pursued. From my freshman year, which began with my interest in computer science, to my senior year, when I completed a degree in philosophy, my grandparents watched me transform from a student interested in mathematical puzzles to a citizen engaged in the world, obsessed with questions about ethics and justice, fascinated by philosophical problems, and convinced, even if na vely so, that education was the answer to all of the world s ills.
Influenced by these discussions, I traded my interest in law to pursue the Master s degree in the Philosophy for Children program. I remain convinced of the program s ability to improve critical thinking and engage young people in philosophical questions such that they are able to find meaning in the world around them and the lives they live. But I am no more convinced that this program is sufficient to make children better people, where better means more ethical, or that my own humanities education made me or any other humanities student a better person.
Engaging the humanities might enable us to be more reflective, to ask critical questions, to consider different perspectives, and to think more creatively. I do not believe, however, that it creates the desire or establishes the motivation for us to act ethically or justly. Yet, the view that the humanities do in fact accomplish this task has become part of humanities education rhetoric. Moreover, this view frames the narrative that is often told to those who are responsible for funding-and frequently suspicious of-higher education. The aim of this book is not to provide a manifesto for or against the humanities. Rather, I wish to take a step back and examine what informs the way an individual might receive that education. Who is this person before she engages the humanities?
When I teach Emmanuel Levinas s philosophical project, the question my students ask me repeatedly is the following: How does one become the ethical subject that Levinas describes? Some might say this is the wrong question to ask. The question presumes that the strict phenomenological reading is limited and that Levinas is not simply describing who we are. After reading his essays on Jewish education alongside his philosophical project, I remain convinced that my students question is precisely the right question to ask. How indeed does someone become an ethical subject?
This book attempts to answer that question by first examining the role that Levinas s essays on Jewish education play in understanding his larger philosophical project. I then consider why Levinas turns to Jewish education and not a classical humanities education to answer this question. There are two simultaneous and possibly competing visions of ethical subjectivity. On the one hand, Levinas is interested in the ethical subject who will not be a murderous self in the first place. Yet, on the other, he is also interested in the person who, like the prophet, will not only see injustice but also cry out against it.
The seeds of this project were planted many years ago, but the trajectory of the project shifted when life events provided the intersection for theory and practice. Several years after I completed my PhD, I was confronted with just such a situation. We do not often get to see our friends or colleagues mettle tested. Depending on how they respond, it can be inspiring or disappointing. The department in which I was a faculty member had imploded. A colleague had been harassing graduate students. My department head reported his behavior to the university Affirmative Action office. About ten days later, he-not the person doing the harassing-was summarily relieved of his headship position. The department fell into chaos and then suffered a series of humiliations including being called whiners by upper administration for demanding that something be done about the bad behavior in the department (one can only wonder about the future success of K-12 programs to stop bullying when those with the highest degrees in education call those who speak out against such behavior whiners ).
I was not yet tenured at the time and I was pregnant with my second baby. I was terrified that my husband (also my tenured colleague) and I might lose our jobs: how would we support ourselves, our two-year-old daughter, and the new baby we would have that fall? Yet, this battle that continued for the next two years also asked me to consider who I am and what kind of person I want to be. Who will my daughters see when they look at me? These are not easy questions to ask of ourselves. Looking back, I remember moments of which I am proud, where I stood strong, where I spoke out, and defended my colleagues. But there were also moments where I fell short, where I thought I had caved. The fight in the university had infected our home and the relationship with our kids-it was time to stop. But we felt that the actions we took to protect our family had also betrayed our friends and colleagues, or at the very least, let them down. The real disappointment, however, was the lack of support and the deafening silence from the larger academic community.
Are injustices that are close to us harder to see? Are they harder to act upon? I remain convinced that for Levinas ethical subjectivity comprises both parts: to see the injustice, to recognize it as such, is to be moved not only to speak out but also to act. His ethical project responds to the Shoah in which he n

  • Univers Univers
  • Ebooks Ebooks
  • Livres audio Livres audio
  • Presse Presse
  • Podcasts Podcasts
  • BD BD
  • Documents Documents