Zizek and Heidegger
7 pages
English

Zizek and Heidegger

Le téléchargement nécessite un accès à la bibliothèque YouScribe
Tout savoir sur nos offres
7 pages
English
Le téléchargement nécessite un accès à la bibliothèque YouScribe
Tout savoir sur nos offres

Description


the essay Zizek wrote on "Why Heidegger Made the Right Step in 1933" has made its way into his newest book, In Defense of Lost Causes--the topic thus merits a reconsideration, but I'll be more brief and more blunt.
Zizek's effort in this book is valiant. One can take this recent and precise characterization of the book by Terry Eagleton (a rarity in Eagleton's corpus--and perhaps the only one in this shallow, resentful review), and affirm it against Eagleton's scorn:
  [Moins]

Informations

Publié par
Nombre de lectures 14
Langue English

Extrait

·
ElousiaSaoirseBarbara
http://books.google.co.uk/books/about/Zizek_and_Heidegger.html? id=xBTWPo80plcC&redir_esc=y
Here’s a little criticism from Thomas Brockelman on Ian Parker. It’s the same Brockelman that has a paper on this current issue of IJZS! “Following Atheism: on a Debate in Contemporary psychoanalytic Theory”.
Brockelman refers to Parker’s book as being one of three important books on Zizek. (The others being Rex Butler’s “Slavoj ZizekL Live Theory” and “Zizek Tony Myers)
“On the other hand, for Parker, Zizek’s style doesn’t so much open a path of interpretation as challenge the very possibility of forging such a direction. We are, he [Parker] claims, too “easily sidetracked or swept along by his anecdotes or jokes,” a tendency to bewitchment that distracts us from the fact that his “intervention around different issues are inconsistent and his theoretical position is contradictory” (Parker 2004, p.2). For Parker, the trick of reading Zizek is not to be “seduced” by the Zizek “reading machine,” by its production of this powerful illusion that there is a “treasure” hidden in Zizek’s writing, awaiting the busy hermeneut willing to uncover it. We must resist the temptation to find a “true Zizek,” beneath the dance of many veils into which he offers to draw us.”
“Though he [Parker] is the least sympathetic to Zizek of all his “introducers” I would also lke to suggest that Parker is also, in a sense, the best of those who begin form style: for he is most honest about where we end up if we make this the starting point of our investigation . That is, through this window we can only see Zizek’s inconsistencies and – which do, of course, exist and make up a part of the “picture” – but we miss the passionate cause that binds both the path of his development and the system of exceptions within it. Furthermore, Parker simply carries to an extreme the judgment that naturally follows from the “stylistic” starting point. He really speaks for a broad consensus in the academic world that admits it’s important to write about Zizek (thus, the steady stream of books and journal articles on his work) but important, also, to dismiss him.”
What is particularly interesting for me in Brockelman’s account of these “introducers” of Zizek’s work: - here’s what he writes: “From my viewpoint, we should take the rush to hold Zizek in an “introductory” format (with its prejudice for disciplinary pluralisation) as just that, a symptomatic effort at containment of a thought which is threatening and anxiety-producing in what is reveals about us.”
And as a friend of mine pointed out in response to the latter Brockelman quotation -this “introductory” of Zizekian thoughts/writing is in some way: -
‘The reconfiguration of Zizek [Zizek’s work] as to something that can be thought as a Symptom’
Something similar came to my mind once (about criticisms of Zizek’s work becoming a Symptom) whilst attending a seminar where there were Psychoanalysts in the throes of criticising Zizek!
Some more from Brockelman later! Tbc.
Zizek and Heidegger
books.google.co.uk
iek and Heidegger offers a radical new interpretation of the work of Slavoj i...Afficher la suite
il y a 18 heures· J’aime ·1
·
Barbara Friedrichstrange, I just posted a comment or thought to have posted it(?) gone in the electronical Nirwana?! Isidore ,I liked very much your link and I'm sure there are many to whom its of interest. And I think it's absolutely necessary for a journal like IJZS to publish works from more critical (towards Zizek) authors. - btw I liked a lot this text from Rex Butler in one of the first issues of IJZS. - And I like this text above,Elousia. Since I'm not obliged to work in Philosophy, to find a thinking position, to elaborate and evaluate this position, and so on and so on and just can't read all, I'manyway obliged to make a choice, of course always very subjective and mostly along links I find here and there... at the moment LTN because Hegel among others is of great interest for me...
·
Barbara Friedrichsome may see the moon,when they looked often enough on the finger?!
·
Jason BoissonneaultIt could be my lack of understanding and familiarity with Lacan, psychoanalysis and Hegelian contradiction, but I remain sceptical about some aspects of this type of material. For instance in "Following Atheism" the first four pages read to me as pure speculation. If I wasn't self-aware of my limitations in knowledge, I would be tempted to dismiss it as "fashionable nonsense" -- until I reach the fifth page, which apparently sums up what I've been attempting to read thus far: "In other words, the world produced by that Enlightenment, with its faith in technical progress and its suspicion of superstition, is itself result of a kind of religion." A fairly simple and straightforward point that comes up in many "New Atheist" discussions. Somehow the previous pages of mind-bendingly abstract
contradiction and speculation constitute evidence of this position which negates any attempt at attacking the nicely-packaged conclusion empirically.
·
Elousia SaoirseThomas Brockelman on Ian Parker - continuation: -
* DOUR IAN PARKER* - & the Pied-Piper Philosopher “leaving them with nothing” [or LESS THAN NOTHING]
“Surely, Parker’s rather exaggerated warnings against the temptation of being “sucked in” by the Zizek-phenomenon, his concern to introduce a kind of prophylaxis between the would-be reader and her text all respond to something like “Zizek Rocks.” The need for protection – he warns against “getting drawn in” by Zizek’s style – shape the very meaning of “introduce” in Parker’s ‘Critical Introduction’ , which comes to mean something like “contextualize” rather than “understand” (Parker 2004, p. 4). Thus, eschewing the temptation to pursue what Zizek means by interpreting his elusive and manic texts. Parker gives us a series of connected essays noting the choices Zizek has made in relationship to various traditions and interlocutors. “Don’t read this at home alone, folks” is the not-so-subtle-message of his book. But isn’t there something odd, something disturbing about the choice suggested by this frame in a text about Zizek’s work? By, that is, the either/or of those “groupie” graduate students and the dour Parker, playing the traditional father in warning the youth against seduction by the enjoyments of Zizekian dissolution? Why won’t Parker READ ZIZEK, choosing instead to inoculate readers against him? The extreme set of precautions against seduction that determine Parker’s strategy is precisely worked out so as to obscure the one possibility THAT Parker refuses to entertain – that we might think through Zizek without being “converted” by him, that we might remain critical while acknowledging a coherent intellectual project. [. . .] Philosophers have ALWAYS BEEN SEDUCERS, always presented a pied-piper’s tune with the potential to lead the “youth” off of the straight and narrow and leaving them with nothing in the end. In this Zizek’s work is no different than Socrates’ was. So, what for Parker makes Zizek so particularly dangerous? Here we should depart from what he would “say” and pay attention to what his book does – which is primarily to reveal a basic anxiety about the possibility of uncovering any truth when faced with Zizek’s dazzling theory. Today – such is Parker’s secret suspicion revealed in his hesitation to read Zizek – there really is no possibility of critique, just a series of exchangeable “viewpoints” shored up with more or less strong rhetoric (and Zizek is nothing if not a great rhetorician) . In other words, “Zizek Rocks!” and “Don’t Read Zizek!” actually express the same philosophical position – one which secretly rejects the possibility of genuine criticism. Either one is drawn in . . . or not. We are back with those dangerous Sophist and their worried Athenian parents.
In other words, any “debate” between Parker and the groupies presupposes something like a shared cynical universe, a constituted precisely as an infinite and homogeneous field of exchangeable “viewpoints.” And, moreover, it presupposes a strange, acknowledge knowledge of that universe, of its basic structures, sufficient to fuel at least an anxiety that
truth will never “out” Zizek speaks of this secret knowledge both as the Spinozististic “wisdom” “sub specie aeternitatis” (Zizek 2003, p. 217) [ . . . ]
NDRL
May 31, 2008
Zizek on Heidegger and Nazism, again
I presented asomewhat detailed responseto this topic a while ago: since then, the essay Zizek wrote on "Why Heidegger Made the Right Step in 1933" has made its way into his newest book,In Defense of Lost Causes--the topic thus merits a reconsideration, but I'll be more brief and more blunt.
Zizek's effort in this book is valiant. One can takethis recent and precise characterization of the bookby Terry Eagleton (a rarity in Eagleton's corpus--and perhaps the only one in this shallow, resentful review), and affirm it against Eagleton's scorn:
The self-consciously outrageous case the book has to argue is that there is a “redemptive” moment to be plucked from such failed revolutionary ventures as Jacobinism, Leninism, Stalinism and Maoism. Žižek is by no means a champion of political terror: the Mao he offers us here, for example, is the mass murderer who mused that “half of China may have to die” in the Great Leap Forward, and who remarked that though a nuclear war might blow a hole in the planet, it would leave the cosmos largely untouched.His aim is not to justify such demented views, but to make things harder for the typical liberal middle-class dismissal of them(my italics).
Perhaps Eagleton phrases it in an asinine way, but I think that this "making things harder" of Zizek is precisely how we should read Zizek's effort. Phrased a little less cynically, we might put Eagleton's statement this way: Zizekrestores weightto politics, philosophy, and culture--this is his mission and has been his mission consistently throughout this career. And rather than losing momentum over the years, he has only become more intense--his ambitions and his fire only have grown. But Eagleton's idiocy locates the problem in this restoration--he makes the same mistake as Zizek, but falls only on the other side of its result. The problem is this: who is the subject to which Zizek addresses his discourse? Granted, unlike other big thinkers on the Left (I'm particularly thinking of certain Frenchmen, with their extraordinary academic and state apparatuses), Zizek's ideas is less institutionally supported in the sense of having a stable and somewhat more closed forum in which to speak--indeed, his best work is when he is among psychoanalysts. But his major works are always more global than that: he is probably the first thoroughly global (and this does not mean international) thinker. This means that his remarks are directed somewhat all over the place. And in the end, who reads them? Well, in the UK and in America, the typical middle-class Anglo-American thinker (I bypass the great and much more fruitful reception he has had elsewhere, and merely talk about our Zizek, the Zizek that we see and talk about here). I'm not saying the people are middle-class who read Zizek. It is that the particular middle-class that Eagleton has in mind is the one sympathized with and identified with by the Left intellectual: the subject needed to be mobilized and enlightened in order to do something substantial about capitalism. Zizek's great achievement is to try and restore some weight to Marxist notions and the Marxist spirit by showing Marxism isn't as old as we thought: it still has life in it yet, because it can link up in a creative way with Lacan--that is, an anti-humanistic (but not Althusserian) thinking. This must resolutely be called "making things harder" only in the sense that this means an ascesis, a training in thinking and in activity so as to be able to adjust thinking to the radically new problems posed by capitalism--those problems which escape the more rigid Marxism of most of the twentieth century. In short, it means thinking about action: Zizek is the thinker of individual and collective action against and within capitalism--if this means things must be harder, it means that we also are on the way to addressing their difficulty by becoming hard. Eagleton cannot know what this means: all he can do is seek out points where real thinkers are complicit in the capitalism they criticize. Thus, where Eagleton would stupidly see some hypocrisy in the precise identity of the Anglo-American subject of Zizek's work (shouldn't Zizek mainly be talking to the rebels?), we can begin to see that the real problem in this identity is that it can only be marshaled into
action by appeals to practicality--or at least this is what Zizek seems to assume (and with some grounds for doing so). The extremely impractical restorative weight that he gives to certain problems, then, ultimately has to turn on almost being able to be confused with the immediately practical: this is the one, sole aspect that constitutes the Zizekian flair in almost every sentence. There is a reversal on a conceptual level that he effects--for example, what Heidegger did in 1933 (join the Nazi party) was not evil, but actually a rare thinking-through of the commitment his philosophy was making politically and one that took place not within that philosophy itself (smuggled into texts) but in action--and this reversal almost of itself can seem to be absolutely pragmatic--it suggests that one should not philosophize politics as much as engage in political action. The force of this reversal is always an appeal to pragmatic action--and this because the audience Zizek writes his sentences for is one that needs not only conceptual shifts and reversals but clues to guide their practical activity. In short, the people Zizek writes for can't just think through a conceptual reversal--they need the force of this reversal to reflect some practical action they can engage in then and there.
While this might be right about these readers, I wonder whether Zizek doesn't need to rethink this aspect of his writings--for in a case like this with Heidegger we see that perhaps another way of arguing and appealing would be both more practical and intellectually interesting. For what is Zizek's treatment of Heidegger, after all? It doesn't say much besides its title: in short, postmodernist philosophers who sneak politics into their words are weak compared to even Heidegger, who had the smarts to join a party in the open, as an action--that is, be committed to what one says even more than theorizing it. Of course this was a monstrous choice--but in principle, with other parties, this is what the Left needs. So Zizek argues, but this is only to isolate what is most obvious about the case of Heidegger: that he made a political decision
which was tied into his thinking. Beyond the shock, the appeal to mobilize in a similarly counterintuitive way (but with a totally different party)--precisely because (according to Zizek) Heidegger's case is a paradigmatic instance of the risks of political engagement for thinkers--this does not do much. And it risks making a sly appeal to the perverse in Heidegger's action as what we should feel if we are being political, if we are being active--it gives us something disturbing that we can be okay with so we can get off our asses and mobilize. In other words, this makes it seem as if the bar is lowered for all of us and that political action is just perverse since it always risks being an abomination. In short, it risks being pragmatic for the sake of being pragmatic--that is, just to mobilize. And it is willing to sacrifice the conclusions for this aim. This is Zizek's fault--and to say this is to be as far away from chastising him as a provocateur as possible. In the end, if Zizek is advocating an action like Heidegger's but directed differently--if he is saying that most political action of thinkers has to risk becoming Heidegger--well I can't see how this isn't a refusal to think what is so vile in Heidegger: the privileging of presence, of activity, of manliness, of the poetic; and the denigrating of the calculating, the prosaic, the everyday--all this, so prevalent in his writings, beingmade intoa Nazism, committed to very specific ideals that are unspeakably disgusting. Many thinkers have had these privileges before: they are not Nazis. And if Zizek is saying that they are precisely not politically engaged because of this--well, he is waging a war not just pragmatically in the now against capitalism, but with a lot of human history. It all comes down to this: is Zizek's discussion of Heidegger an example for a revolutionary mind? Or is it something more impractical? If it is the latter, well, I don't know how we would read Zizek.
Posted by Mike Johnduff
What is written about:Heidegger,Nazism,Politics,Zizek
  • Univers Univers
  • Ebooks Ebooks
  • Livres audio Livres audio
  • Presse Presse
  • Podcasts Podcasts
  • BD BD
  • Documents Documents