Simone Weil
143 pages
English

Vous pourrez modifier la taille du texte de cet ouvrage

Découvre YouScribe en t'inscrivant gratuitement

Je m'inscris

Simone Weil , livre ebook

-
traduit par

Découvre YouScribe en t'inscrivant gratuitement

Je m'inscris
Obtenez un accès à la bibliothèque pour le consulter en ligne
En savoir plus
143 pages
English

Vous pourrez modifier la taille du texte de cet ouvrage

Obtenez un accès à la bibliothèque pour le consulter en ligne
En savoir plus

Description

Although trained as a philosopher, Simone Weil (1909–43) contributed to a wide range of subjects, resulting in a rich field of interdisciplinary Weil studies. Yet those coming to her work from such disciplines as sociology, history, political science, religious studies, French studies, and women’s studies are often ignorant of or baffled by her philosophical investigations. In Simone Weil: Late Philosophical Writings, Eric O. Springsted presents a unique collection of Weil’s writings, one concentrating on her explicitly philosophical thinking.

The essays are drawn chiefly from the time Weil spent in Marseille in 1940-42, as well as one written from London; most have been out of print for some time; three appear for the first time; all are newly translated. Beyond making important texts available, this selection provides the context for understanding Weil's thought as a whole. This volume is important not only for those with a general interest in Weil; it also specifically presents Weil as a philosopher, chiefly one interested in questions of the nature of value, moral thought, and the relation of faith and reason. What also appears through this judicious selection is an important confirmation that on many issues respecting the nature of philosophy, Weil, Wittgenstein, and Kierkegaard shared a great deal.


Sujets

Informations

Publié par
Date de parution 15 septembre 2015
Nombre de lectures 2
EAN13 9780268092917
Langue English
Poids de l'ouvrage 2 Mo

Informations légales : prix de location à la page 0,1000€. Cette information est donnée uniquement à titre indicatif conformément à la législation en vigueur.

Extrait

Edited and with an introduction by ERIC O. SPRINGSTED
SIMONE WEIL
Late Philosophical Writings
Translated by ERIC O. SPRINGSTED and LAWRENCE E. SCHMIDT
University of Notre Dame Press
Notre Dame, Indiana
Copyright © 2015 by the University of Notre Dame
Notre Dame, Indiana 46556
undpress.nd.edu
All Rights Reserved
E-ISBN 978-0-268-09291-7
This e-Book was converted from the original source file by a third-party vendor. Readers who notice any formatting, textual, or readability issues are encouraged to contact the publisher at ebooks@nd.edu Manufactured in the United States of America Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Weil, Simone, 1909–1943. [Works. Selections. English. 2015] Late philosophical writings / Simone Weil; edited and with an introduction by Eric O. Springsted; translated by Eric O. Springsted and Lawrence E. Schmidt. pages cm Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 978-0-268-04150-2 (pbk.: alk. paper) ISBN 0-268-04150-4 (pbk.: alk. paper) I. Springsted, Eric O., editor. II. Title. B2430.W472E55 2015 194—dc23 2015017676 ∞ The paper in this book meets the guidelines for permanence and durability of the Committee on Production Guidelines for Book Longevity of the Council on Library Resources. -->
Contents
Notes on the Texts and Acknowledgments
Introduction: Simone Weil on Philosophy
ONE. Essay on the Concept of Reading
TWO. Some Reflections on the Concept of Value: On Valéry’s Claim That Philosophy Is Poetry
THREE. Philosophy
FOUR. God in Plato
FIVE. Notes on the Concept of Character
SIX. What Is Sacred in Every Human Being?
SEVEN. The First Condition for the Work of a Free Person ( Translated by Lawrence E. Schmidt )
EIGHT. Literature and Morals
NINE. The Responsibilities of Literature
TEN. At the Price of an Infinite Error: The Scientific Image, Ancient and Modern Index -->
Notes on the Texts and Acknowledgments
With the exception of “What Is Sacred in Every Human Being?,” which comes from the time Weil was in London in 1943, all of the texts presented here were written during her time in Marseille—September 1940 to May 1942. The texts used are the ones established and published in the Oeuvres complètes IV.1 and IV.2 (Paris: Gallimard, 2008, 2009), again excepting “What Is Sacred in Every Human Being?,” which comes from Écrits de Londres (Paris: Gallimard, 1957). In the case of three essays, the Oeuvres complètes edition varies from earlier editions, most notably in a number of additional pages included in “At the Price of an Infinite Error: The Scientific Image, Ancient and Modern,” the arrangement of various paragraphs in “God in Plato,” and some small changes in “The First Condition for the Work of a Free Person,” where Weil’s original is restored after certain editorial changes had been made by the publication for which that essay was intended. This is the first English edition of these essays in their complete and corrected form.
Three essays are also translated and published in book form in English for the first time here: “Essay on the Concept of Reading,” “Some Reflections on the Concept of Value,” and “Notes on the Concept of Character.”
Titles in some cases have been changed from their first English translation. “Human Personality” is here “What Is Sacred in Every Human Being?”; “Morality and Literature” is “Literature and Morals”; “The Responsibility of Writers” is “The Responsibilities of Literature”; “The First Condition of Non-Servile Work” is “The First Condition for the Work of a Free Person”; “Classical Science and After” is “At the Price of an Infinite Error: The Scientific Image, Ancient and Modern.”
The translation of “Some Reflections on the Concept of Value” was originally published in Philosophical Investigations 37.2 (2014): 105–12, and is reprinted by permission of Wiley-Blackwell.
I would like to thank Lawrence Schmidt for his kind and gracious offer to include his translation of “The First Condition for the Work of a Free Person.” I would also like to thank my longtime friend and philosophical correspondent, Stephen Goldman, for his reading of several of these translations, his suggestions, and above all for the conversation that followed.
Introduction
Simone Weil on Philosophy
It can be highly misleading to separate out a complex thinker’s works too neatly into discrete subjects if one wants to understand the thinker herself. This is especially the case with somebody such as Simone Weil. Her works cover philosophy, history, social matters (such as justice, labor, and politics), mysticism, world religions, and subjects belonging to Christian theology. Valuable as these insights may be to those fields individually, there is an intellectual character to all of them that clearly shows they come from a single, and singular, mind. The insights are valuable in themselves, but the thinker transcends them. For anyone to say who Weil is as a thinker, and what she has to teach anybody, and to say it accurately, much less well, one ultimately has to take into consideration all of her work as a whole and its complex overlapping.
Still, it can be a very helpful exercise to take up the question of Weil’s thinking about philosophy as a particular subject, that is, to take up what she thought thinking is and ought to be and hence what she thought she was doing in writing all that she did. It is to take up what she thought the value of her work was and, as it turns out, what her thinking on value was.
But in treating what Weil thought philosophy is, we need to be careful about what exactly we are doing. Numerous books and articles on Weil have treated her from a philosophical point of view. But doing so can present certain problems, most generally when one fails to see where her interests and concerns go far beyond what academic philosophers normally treat. There are a number of places where this happens. Above all, to approach her in a strictly philosophical way will often completely miss—often deliberately—a genuine and central theological commitment in Simone Weil the thinker, or will miss it as a theological or religious commitment. Her Christianity, as unorthodox as it often appears, is not an addendum or a conclusion to a chain of reasoning from elsewhere. For her, there really is an act of God that takes place in Christ’s Incarnation and Crucifixion that determines the nature of the world and of human beings. This conviction was something she herself admits that she came by unexpectedly through personal experience, and not by a process of reasoning. She even goes so far as to suggest that her reason wasn’t quite sure what to do with what was indeed a certitude in her life. Yet, lest one mistake things on the other side, it also needs to be understood that this religious commitment does not make serious and unremitting philosophical reflection beside the point for Weil. Far from it. She is not just an anthology of mystical insights. So, how this commitment and philosophy go together is of the first order for understanding Weil. It is a matter of getting it right on both sides of the equation.
A second mistake occurs when one treats her as a philosopher in the sense that she is somebody who produces a philosophy. This is more than a problem of ignoring the obvious and oft-repeated fact that Weil is not a systematic thinker. Even though she is not, she is not an incoherent thinker, and what she says in one place often really does have bearing on what she says elsewhere. She thinks in a highly analogical way and finds some very startling and striking connections between otherwise disparate areas of thought. For this reason, it really is possible to provide some sort of conceptual map of the distinctive parts of her thinking. It is possible to teach somebody what significant things she has to say, and it is possible to show a person how to move from one concept to another in her thought. She is not an oracle. Rather, the mistake comes in thinking that once one has provided such a map that one has said what she was trying to do as a philosopher. For example, one might be tempted once such a map has been drawn then to compare her various “positions” as a philosopher with those of other philosophers. Though she has startling and discernible positions, one might be tempted to think that such positions are what she thinks philosophers ought to be coming up with, and that philosophy, as it is in the academy, is a matter of continually arguing for and against these positions. One can see where this has happened in treating Weil, even from the very beginning of the secondary literature on her. For example, Miklos Vetö, in his early and still very helpful The Religious Metaphysics of Simone Weil , provides a way to navigate around Weil’s thinking that is quite accurate and insightful. 1 He is also quite helpful in regularly pointing out the degree to which Weil was indebted to Plato and to Kant. But Vetö also was insistent that Weil was a “classical metaphysician,” which is to say, he thinks that she was doing something like building a position, and that not only can one compare it to others, say, Kant, but that one intellectually ought to be doing that. But that is exactly what is at stake, at least insofar as Weil herself saw the nature of philosophy, because she did not think philosophy was that at all.
Finally, one can also make a related mistake by thinking that in uncovering her “metaphysics” one has uncovered the ultimate grounds for everything else she has to say, that one has somehow gotten “behind” what she says to find something like a theory that explains her various positions, or that somehow causes them, or that somebody else could use to build an intellectual position. Such a theory, of course, would constitute the ultimate meaning of her philosophical work, and what she has to say as a whole would then stand or fall on that. But again this is not how she thought.
So, with these caveats, it will be helpful

  • Univers Univers
  • Ebooks Ebooks
  • Livres audio Livres audio
  • Presse Presse
  • Podcasts Podcasts
  • BD BD
  • Documents Documents