David Hume
88 pages
English

Vous pourrez modifier la taille du texte de cet ouvrage

Découvre YouScribe en t'inscrivant gratuitement

Je m'inscris

Découvre YouScribe en t'inscrivant gratuitement

Je m'inscris
Obtenez un accès à la bibliothèque pour le consulter en ligne
En savoir plus
88 pages
English

Vous pourrez modifier la taille du texte de cet ouvrage

Obtenez un accès à la bibliothèque pour le consulter en ligne
En savoir plus

Description

In the first book of its kind, Bernard Freydberg places David Hume firmly in the tradition of the Platonic dialogues, and regards him as a proper ancestor of contemporary continental philosophy. Although Hume is largely confined to his historical context within British Empiricism, his skepticism resonates with the Socratic Ignorance expressed by Plato, and his account of experience points toward very contemporary concerns in continental thought. Through close readings of An Enquiry Concerning the Human Understanding, An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, and the essay "On the Standard of Taste," Freydberg traces a philosophy of imagination that will set the stage for wider consideration of Hume within continental thought.
Acknowledgments

Introduction

Deleuze’s Hume...and Ours: Madness, Retrieval

1. Aspects of An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding

2. Aspects of An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals

3. Hume’s Philosophy of Art

Conclusion

Notes
Index

Sujets

Informations

Publié par
Date de parution 21 mai 2012
Nombre de lectures 3
EAN13 9781438442167
Langue English

Informations légales : prix de location à la page 0,1498€. Cette information est donnée uniquement à titre indicatif conformément à la législation en vigueur.

Extrait

SUNY series in Contemporary Continental Philosophy

Dennis J. Schmidt, editor

David Hume
Platonic Philosopher, Continental Ancestor
BERNARD FREYDBERG

On the cover are details from Views of the Bosphorus: Views of the Bosphorus: Sariyer , 2011, 20″h × 40″w, bamboo stitched on paper. Views of the Bosphorus: Istinye , 2011, 20″h × 40″w, bamboo stitched on paper. Views of the Bosphorus: Sea of Marmara , 2011, 20″h × 40″w, bamboo stitched on paper.
Published by State University of New York Press, Albany
© 2012 State University of New York
All rights reserved
Printed in the United States of America
No part of this book may be used or reproduced in any manner whatsoever without written permission. No part of this book may be stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means including electronic, electrostatic, magnetic tape, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise without the prior permission in writing of the publisher.
For information, contact State University of New York Press, Albany, NY www.sunypress.edu
Production by Ryan Morris Marketing by Kate McDonnell
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Freydberg, Bernard, 1947–
David Hume : platonic philosopher, continental ancestor / Bernard Freydberg.
p. cm. — (SUNY series in contemporary continental philosophy)
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 978-1-4384-4215-0 (hardcover : alk. paper)
1. Hume, David, 1711–1776. I. Title.
B1498.F74 2012
192—dc23
2011023763
10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1

For Dennis J Schmidt:
Original Thinker, Friend to Philosophy and Philosophers
Acknowledgments
The following people and institutions supported the writing of this book in various ways. I thank them, one and all, more than I can say.
I was blessed with two terrific editors at the State University of New York Press. Jane Bunker, Editor in Chief, with whom I began this book before she moved on to the directorship at Northwestern University Press, is a brilliant editor and a brilliant human being. Given her background in philosophy, her support for this book gave me much confidence. Andrew Kenyon, now Assistant Acquisitions Editor and in charge of philosophy books, has been a delight to work with.
Sami Gülgöz, Dean of the School of Social Sciences and Humanities at Koç University, Istanbul, approved a leave for the summer of 2008 that made the research and part of the writing of this book possible. Shannon Sullivan, Chair of the Pennsylvania State University Philosophy Department, granted me the position of Visiting Scholar for that same summer. This enabled me to avail myself of the wonderful Penn State libraries and other facilities. James Swindal, Chair of the Duquesne University Philosophy Department, graciously appointed me Scholar in Residence, the post I now occupy. I completed the book under his and its aegis.
Two anonymous readers for the State University of New York Press provided me with reviews that combined encouragement with astute criticism. A long conversation with Jennifer Mensch of the Penn State Philosophy Department on pre-Kantian philosophy was most illuminating. Michael Rudar and John Fritz, two of my former undergraduate philosophy students who are completing their PhD degrees at Duquesne University, proofread and offered helpful comments on the manuscript. Both will surely be excellent professors before too long.
Kathleen Manning and Rita McClelland of Bailey Library at Slippery Rock University were, as they have been in the past, exceptionally helpful in securing materials for this book. One could not hope for better librarians.
My wife, Akiko Kotani, inspires me in every way. Once again, her view as an artist on imagination has influenced my own, and she is a marvelous partner in all that I attempt. My daughter, Malika Hadley Freydberg, also gives me wings by virtue of her intelligence and great spirit.
Dennis J. Schmidt has made important contributions to philosophy on every level. His scholarly work always breaks new ground. He has regularly had a prominent role in organizing important conferences and events. As a teacher, he presents lectures and conducts that challenge, encourage, and open new pathways for his hearers. As editor of this series, he has overseen the publication of more than one hundred Continental philosophy books over the years. My debt is to him considerable, and it is an honor to be his colleague. With humility and great pleasure, I dedicate this book to him.
Introduction
My ambition for this book is large. With it, I seek to locate David Hume incontestably as a most worthy ancestor of and for Continental philosophy. While his thought receives occasional treatment, especially in Husserl, and while Deleuze's 1953 Empiricism and Subjectivity : An Essay on Hume's Theory of Human Nature provides a daring and valuable reading of the Treatise of Human Nature , 1 no single book in the Continental tradition (at least to my knowledge) attempts an overview of Hume's philosophy in terms of its major developments in interpretation. Among these, I consider especially Heidegger's of Kant, Merleau-Ponty's of Husserl, and Sallis's of Plato (as well as of many others). These interpretations combine scrupulous regard for the texts with creative excavations yielding heretofore untapped resources. Happy indeed (as Hume would write) if in this book such fine scholarship joins with such worthy novel insights!
I find an inspiration for this task in a well-known turning point in philosophy's history. According to my view, the greatest Hume scholar to date and perhaps forever is Immanuel Kant. In his time, he alone grasped the radicality and the force of his Scottish forbear's thought. After denouncing the obtuse responses of Reid, Oswald, Beatty, and Priestly to Hume, he famously wrote in the Prolegomena :
I openly confess my recollection of David Hume was the very thing that many years ago first interrupted my dogmatic slumber and gave my investigations in the field of speculative philosophy a quite new direction. 2
The word recollection is hardly innocent in philosophy. While one cannot make any direct connection between Kantian and Platonic recollection (though Kant knew Greek well, and undoubtedly read Plato in both Greek and German), I venture to assert at least a strong analogy 3 : Along with the voluminous contents in the soul of Kant, there dwelled the arguments of Hume. With suddenness at some point, Kant saw how powerfully his thought challenged both modern rationalism and modern empiricism—just as it challenged his own lifelong efforts as a metaphysician. It is impossible to fix the precise date at which he experienced the full power of Hume's insight, but his Inaugural Dissertation, which still contained traces of rational metaphysics, was delivered in 1777 when he was fifty-three years old, and the Critique of Pure Reason first appeared in 1781.
The central Transcendental Deduction took many years and much labor to complete. The framework and the setting of the problem can be found in Kant's 1772 well-known letter to Markus Herz:
[A]s to how my understanding may form for itself concepts of things completely a priori, with which concepts the things must necessarily agree, and as to how my understanding may formulate real principles concerning the possibility of such concepts, and experience must faithfully agree with these principles which nevertheless are independent of experience—this question, of how the faculty of understanding achieves this conformity with the things themselves, is still left in a state of obscurity. 4
In his November 14, 1776, letter to Herz, Kant indicated that while he would likely be unable to complete the Critique before Easter, he “shall use part of next summer for it.” 5 “[P]art of next summer” became four years.
There can be no doubt that Hume hovered over all of Kant's labors, making them more arduous at every turn. Testimony of Hume's influence could not be more compelling given the still lively, penetrating, and spirited interpretations of the Transcendental Deduction (A edition, B edition, and both together). As a lover who's brave enough to take on lost causes and articulate them with skill, I mention Gottfried Martin's 1953 Immanuel Kant, Ontologie und Wissenschaftstheorie (translated as Kant's Metaphysics and Theory of Science ), 6 whose articulation is all the more remarkable as a result of what he does not say. The name Hume appears nowhere in it, making it unique and, to employ an admittedly much overused cliché, establishing the exception that proves the rule. Yet another: Hume is the elephant in the room on every page. If there were no Hume, it is difficult if not impossible to imagine a critical philosophy of Kant.
Although many Hume scholars recognize the importance of imagination to his thought, 7 none to my knowledge read Hume such that the generation of images is the sine qua non of his theoretical and practical thought, and that this aspect has primary importance for Kant's response; nor do any regard this aspect as a source for Continental philosophy. My primary purpose is to raise the all-important matter of imagination , tracing it from Hume through Kant and farther in the Continental tradition, where it begins to lose its centrality after Schelling for more than a century. In my view, it is the preeminent faculty or function: it generates fictions that can become beliefs, it is the freest device of all, and—more to the point—imagination alone makes possible and empowers the transition between past constant conjunctions to the unavoidable supposition to their continuation in the future, the sole basis of that fiction-become-belief that we call cause and effect.
One could say with justification that it was Hume's analysis of the concept of cause and effect, treating it as is fundamentally fictional, 8 that jolted Kant awake. But this means that the curious “new impression” produced by imagination after

  • Univers Univers
  • Ebooks Ebooks
  • Livres audio Livres audio
  • Presse Presse
  • Podcasts Podcasts
  • BD BD
  • Documents Documents