Plato and the Body
161 pages
English

Vous pourrez modifier la taille du texte de cet ouvrage

Découvre YouScribe en t'inscrivant gratuitement

Je m'inscris

Plato and the Body , livre ebook

Découvre YouScribe en t'inscrivant gratuitement

Je m'inscris
Obtenez un accès à la bibliothèque pour le consulter en ligne
En savoir plus
161 pages
English

Vous pourrez modifier la taille du texte de cet ouvrage

Obtenez un accès à la bibliothèque pour le consulter en ligne
En savoir plus

Description

For centuries, it has been the prevailing view that in prioritizing the soul, Plato ignores or even abhors the body; however, in Plato and the Body Coleen P. Zoller argues that Plato does value the body and the role it plays in philosophical life, focusing on Plato's use of Socrates as an exemplar. Zoller reveals a more refined conception of the ascetic lifestyle epitomized by Socrates in Plato's Phaedo, Symposium, Phaedrus, Gorgias, and Republic. Her interpretation illuminates why those who want to be wise and good have reason to be curious about and love the natural world and the bodies in it, and has implications for how we understand Plato's metaphysical and political commitments. This book shows the relevance of this broader understanding of Plato for work on a variety of relevant contemporary issues, including sexual morality, poverty, wealth inequality, and peace.
Acknowledgments

1. Interpreting Asceticism in Plato

2. Moderation and Training for Death in the Phaedo

3. Beauty, Education, and Erotic Ascent in the Symposium and Phaedrus

4. Health, Justice, and Peace in the Republic and Gorgias

5. Interpretative Possibilities for the Late Dialogues

Epilogue
Notes
Works Cited
Index

Sujets

Informations

Publié par
Date de parution 11 juillet 2018
Nombre de lectures 0
EAN13 9781438470832
Langue English

Informations légales : prix de location à la page 0,1648€. Cette information est donnée uniquement à titre indicatif conformément à la législation en vigueur.

Extrait

Plato and the Body
SUNY series in Ancient Greek Philosophy

Anthony Preus, editor
Plato and the Body
Reconsidering Socratic Asceticism
Coleen P. Zoller
Cover art: Stavros Kotsireas, The Refugees , 1988. Reprinted with permission.
Published by State University of New York Press, Albany
© 2018 State University of New York
All rights reserved
Printed in the United States of America
No part of this book may be used or reproduced in any manner whatsoever without written permission. No part of this book may be stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means including electronic, electrostatic, magnetic tape, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise without the prior permission in writing of the publisher.
For information, contact State University of New York Press, Albany, NY
www.sunypress.edu
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Names: Zoller, Coleen P.
Title: Plato and the body : reconsidering socratic asceticism / Coleen P. Zoller.
Description: Albany : State University of New York Press, [2018] | Series: SUNY series in ancient Greek philosophy | Includes bibliographical references and index.
Identifiers: LCCN 2017044461 | ISBN 9781438470818 (hardcover : alk. paper) | ISBN 9781438470832 (ebook)
Subjects: LCSH: Plato. | Asceticism. | Socrates.
Classification: LCC B398.A8 Z65 2018 | DDC 184—dc23
LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2017044461
10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1
For Jeff Turner, my Socratic interlocutor, mentor, and friend
Contents
Acknowledgments Chapter 1. Interpreting Asceticism in Plato Chapter 2. Moderation and Training for Death in the Phaedo Chapter 3. Beauty, Education, and Erotic Ascent in the Symposium and Phaedrus Chapter 4. Health, Justice, and Peace in the Republic and Gorgias Chapter 5. Interpretative Possibilities for the Late Dialogues
Epilogue
Notes
Works Cited
Index
Acknowledgments
M y greatest debt is to Jeff Turner, who graciously read innumerable drafts and shared incredibly insightful guidance at every stage of my project. I also wish to thank the following mentors, colleagues, students, and friends for helpful feedback as I developed my manuscript: Richard Patterson, Roslyn Weiss, Mitch Miller, William Johnson, Tony Long, Tom Chance, Ed Lee, Tarik Wareh, Amy Coplan, Carol Wayne White, Sarah Farrant, Alissa Packer, Rabbi Nina Mandel, James Powers-Black, Karla Bohmbach, Lynn Palermo, Brian Johnson, Emily Anderson, Tom Stanley, students in my Plato seminars at Susquehanna University, audiences at various conferences and colloquia, and my anonymous readers and the editors at SUNY Press. I am particularly grateful to Courtney Radel and Jessica Gilchrist for their work as summer research assistants and to Susquehanna University for the 2014–16 grants that made their research possible. And much gratitude to Courtney Radel for compiling the index. Finally, many thanks to pictorial artist Stavros Kotsireas for permission to use his etching “The Refugees” as cover art.
Some pages of already published work appear here. I would like to thank the following for permission to reprint this material: Cambridge Scholars Press for excerpts from Zoller (2007) in chapters 1 , 2 , and 3 ; University of Malta Press for excerpts from Zoller (2010) in chapters 1 , 2 , and 3 ; and Lexington Books for excerpts from Zoller (2009) in chapters 1 and 4 .
Chapter 1
Interpreting Asceticism in Plato
1.1 Loving Wisdom and Living in a Body
M any commentators have assumed that Plato is responsible for originating the view that loving wisdom is incongruous with being embodied. For instance, many feminists are critical of what they call Plato’s “somatophobia” and take his dualistic metaphysical worldview to be incompatible with feminism. 1 And at the opposite end of the political spectrum, Strauss also accuses Plato of ignoring the body, erôs, and nature. 2 However, we are missing something about his dialogues when we accuse Plato of beginning the tradition that suppresses the importance of the physical in the life of the philosopher or any human being. My primary aim in this project is to offer insight into Plato’s nuanced attitude toward the physical universe in general, and human bodies in particular, because this pertains to his understanding of what philosophy is and what philosophers do. As Plato developed what we now call philosophy, he set a framework that involves analytical thought in addition to a particular kind of lifestyle. Yet, on account of a caricature of his views concerning the physical, Plato is often named as the originator of an embarrassing view of embodied life.
One of Plato’s main goals is to use his character Socrates 3 as an exemplar of the philosopher’s special and rare nature. He has Socrates call himself a philosopher ( Ap. 29d, Phd . 61a); and in most of his dialogues, Plato demonstrates that by observing Socrates we can learn about the lifestyle that is conducive to inquiry. But Plato’s Socrates is not a simple character; his peculiar words and deeds are not always easy to interpret. Among the many complex aspects of Plato’s Socrates is his remarkable self-discipline, what the Greeks would call askesis (practice; training). His self-discipline is highlighted in the dialogues, dovetailing with his desire to pursue knowledge and do what he thinks is best. Socrates’s conversations with his interlocutors sometimes tempt us to believe that doing the right thing is easy when one has knowledge of what is best. However, Plato’s Socrates usually claims not to have any substantial knowledge ( Ap. 21b-d). This leaves Plato’s readers at a bit of a loss with respect to the exact nature of Socrates’s self-discipline. Many Platonic dialogues aim at the vindication of Socrates and philosophy, both of which can be difficult to understand. My project focuses on cultivating a more refined conception of the ascetic lifestyle epitomized by Plato’s Socrates in the Phaedo , Symposium , Phaedrus , Gorgias , and Republic . 4
Who is Plato’s Socrates? This book will remind us that he is a philosopher deeply engaged in worldly matters, who uses his body to enjoy eating ( Smp . 220a) and drinking ( Smp . 220a), to sleep peacefully ( Crt . 44a; Prt . 310b-c; Smp . 223d), to have sexual intercourse, to create a family ( Ap . 34d; Crt . 60a), to participate in democracy, serving his community as a gadfly, a soldier ( Smp . 219e; Chrm . 153b-d), and a member of the Council ( Ap . 32b-c), to stand up to tyranny ( Ap . 32d-e), to look after his circle of friends, to walk daily to the agora, to stroll the outskirts of Athens and observe the beauty of nature ( Phdr . 229a-b), to travel to Piraeus for a religious festival ( R . 327a), to adore beautiful people ( Smp . 212c, 216d, 218e; Prt . 309a-b, 316a; Chrm . 153d-154d, 155d), to flirt ( Phdr . 234d, 237a-b, Smp . 213d, Chrm . 156a), to be in love with Alcibiades ( Grg . 481d), to follow his erotic passion for ideas and virtues. Is this down-to-earth life consistent with his asceticism?
For the sake of uncovering Plato’s vision of how human beings who want to be wise and good should be disposed toward the physical world and the human body, we must understand Plato’s answers to the following questions: What attitudes and dispositions do wisdom lovers have? How exactly do philosophers care for the soul, and what treatment of the body does that psychic care 5 dictate? In what sorts of activities do philosophers participate? What do they value, and why? Or, to put it generally, what sort of lifestyle is entailed by the askesis of which Socrates is an exemplar? Plato’s answers to these kinds of questions reflect his sense of the standards of philosophy. Here I will try to clarify Plato’s account of these matters without being constrained by the need to conform to the interpretation of Platonism that became conventional, which is linked especially to the Phaedo. As Roochnik writes, “This dialogue gives voice to what is surely the most familiar characterization of Platonic philosophy: it is a quest for an ‘otherworldly’ wisdom, for a realm far above, and superior to, the earthly and mortal.” 6 Like Roochnik, I challenge some of the fundamental assumptions about Plato made by those who espouse the most traditional interpretation of Platonic philosophy as otherworldly. 7
In this introductory chapter, I will compare and contrast two interpretations of asceticism; briefly examine some consequences of misinterpreting Socratic asceticism, especially for women, people of color, the other animals, and nature itself; examine the analogical reasoning Plato relies on to advance innovative claims; consider the transformation of vernacular that arises out of Plato’s use of analogical reasoning; call attention to Plato’s use of pedagogical irony; and lay out the plan for the other chapters.
1.2 Two Interpretations of Socratic Asceticism
Conceiving of the soul as what animates the material stuff of the body causes Plato to consider the soul a human being’s true self. 8 As a result, he is deeply concerned with how one ought to think of and treat the soul. Nevertheless, throughout the dialogues Plato makes clear that the question of how one should be disposed toward the soul is very much intertwined with the question of how one ought to handle the body, especially given that Plato’s dialogues indicate that the largest aspect of the soul, the appetite, is charged with wanting what the human body needs to survive. Some of the appetite’s pleasures come from restoration in the body, and although appetite belongs to the soul, the appetite in particular, and soul in general, could not be more essentially connected with the body. It is misguided to think the soul can be properly cared for while the body is renounced, and I will demonstrate that Plato does not make this mistake as some critics have thought.
A widespread and popular characterization of Plato assumes that his dualistic metaphysics requires the renunci

  • Univers Univers
  • Ebooks Ebooks
  • Livres audio Livres audio
  • Presse Presse
  • Podcasts Podcasts
  • BD BD
  • Documents Documents