The Pragmatic Turn in Philosophy
269 pages
English

Découvre YouScribe en t'inscrivant gratuitement

Je m'inscris

The Pragmatic Turn in Philosophy , livre ebook

Découvre YouScribe en t'inscrivant gratuitement

Je m'inscris
Obtenez un accès à la bibliothèque pour le consulter en ligne
En savoir plus
269 pages
English
Obtenez un accès à la bibliothèque pour le consulter en ligne
En savoir plus

Description

The Pragmatic Turn in Philosophy explores how the various discursive strategies of old and new pragmatisms are related, and what their pertinence is to the relationship between pragmatism and philosophy as a whole. The contributors bridge the divide between analytic and continental philosophy through a transcontinental desire to work on common problems in a common philosophical language. Irrespective of which side of the divide one stands on, pragmatic philosophy has gained ascendancy over the traditional concerns of a representationalist epistemology that has determined much of the intellectual and cultural life of modernity. This book details how contemporary philosophy will emerge from this recognition and that, in fact, this emergence is already underway.

Introduction
Mike Sandbothe and William Egginton

1. The Insistence on Futurity: Pragmatism's Temporal Structure
Ludwig Nagl

2. Philosophy as a Reconstructive Activity: William James on Moral Philosophy
Hilary Putnam

3. Pragmatic Aspects of Hegel's Thought
Antje Gimmler

4. The Pragmatic Twist of the Linguistic Turn
Mike Sandbothe

5. The Debate About Truth: Pragmatism without Regulative Ideas
Albrecht Wellmer

6. The Viewpoint of No One in Particular
Arthur Fine

7. A Pragmatist View of Contemporary Analytic Philosophy
Richard Rorty

8. What Knowledge? What Hope? What New Pragmatism?
Barry Allen

9. Richard Rorty: Philosophy Beyond Argument and Truth?
Wolfgang Welsch

10. Keeping Pragmatism Pure: Rorty with Lacan
William Egginton

11. Cartesian Realism and the Revival of Pragmatism
Joseph Margolis

Selected Bibliography

List of Contributors

Index

Sujets

Informations

Publié par
Date de parution 01 février 2012
Nombre de lectures 0
EAN13 9780791485132
Langue English
Poids de l'ouvrage 1 Mo

Informations légales : prix de location à la page 0,1648€. Cette information est donnée uniquement à titre indicatif conformément à la législation en vigueur.

Extrait

THE PRAGMATIC TURN IN PHILOSOPHY
This page intentionally left blank.
THE PRAGMATICTURN IN PHILOSOPHY
Contemporary Engagements between Analytic and Continental Thought
Edited by William Egginton and Mike Sandbothe
S T A T E U N I V E R S I T Y O F N E W Y O R K P R E S S
Published by State University of New York Press, Albany
© 2004 State University of New York
All rights reserved
Printed in the United States of America
No part of this book may be used or reproduced in any manner whatsoever without written permission. No part of this book may be stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means including electronic, electrostatic, magnetic tape, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise without the prior permission in writing of the publisher.
For information, address State University of New York Press, 90 State Street, Suite 700, Albany, NY 12207
Production by Diane Ganeles Marketing by Michael Campochiaro
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
The pragmatic turn in philosophy : contemporary engagements between analytic and Continental thought / edited by William Egginton and Mike Sandbothe. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references (p. ) and index. ISBN 0-7914-6069-X (alk. paper) ISBN 0-7914-6070-3 (pbk.: alk. paper) 1. Pragmatism—History—21st century. 2. Pragmatism—History. 3. Philosophy—History—21st century. I. Egginton, William, 1969– II. Sandbothe, Mike, 1961–
B832.P7525 2004 144'.3—dc22
10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1
2003059026
Contents
Introduction Mike Sandbothe and William Egginton
1.The Insistence on Futurity: Pragmatism’s Temporal Structure Ludwig Nagl 2.Philosophy as a Reconstructive Activity: William James on Moral Philosophy Hilary Putnam 3.Pragmatic Aspects of Hegel’s Thought Antje Gimmler 4.The Pragmatic Twist of the Linguistic Turn Mike Sandbothe 5.The Debate about Truth: Pragmatism without Regulative Ideas Albrecht Wellmer 6.The Viewpoint of No One in Particular Arthur Fine 7.A Pragmatist View of Contemporary Analytic Philosophy Richard Rorty 8.What Knowledge? What Hope? What New Pragmatism? Barry Allen 9.Richard Rorty: Philosophy beyond Argument and Truth? Wolfgang Welsch 10.Keeping Pragmatism Pure: Rorty with Lacan William Egginton
v
1
11
31
47
67
93
115
131
145
163
187
vi
Contents
11.Cartesian Realism and the Revival of Pragmatism Joseph Margolis
Selected Bibliography List of Contributors Index
223
249 257 259
Introduction
n recent years the classical authors of Anglo-Saxon pragmatism have gar-I nered a renewed importance in international philosophical circles. In the aftermath of the linguistic turn, philosophers such as Charles S. Peirce, William James, George H. Mead, Ferdinand C. S. Schiller, and John Dewey are being reread alongside, for example, recent postmodern and deconstructivist thought as alternatives to a traditional orientation toward the concerns of a represen-tationalist epistemology. In the context of contemporary continental thought, the work of Jacques Derrida, Jean-Francois Lyotard, and Gilles Deleuze comprises just a few examples of a culturewide assault on a metaphysical worldview premised on what Michel Foucault called the empirico-transcendental doublet, and presents a wealth of potential exchange with the pragmatist critique of representationalism. In both cases, aspects of pragmatist thought are being used to add flexibility to the conceptual tools of modern philoso-phy, in order to promote a style of philosophizing more apt to dealing with the problems of everyday life. The hope for a pragmatic “renewing of phi-losophy” (Putnam) evidenced in these trends has led to an analytic reexami-nation of some of the fundamental positions in modern continental thought as well, and to a recognitio n of pre viousl y unac knowledged or underappreciated pragmatic elements in thinkers like Kant, Hegel, Nietzsche, Heidegger, and Wittgenstein. Within the current analytic discussions, a wide spectrum of differing and at times completely heterogeneous forms ofneopragmatism can be distinguished, which for heuristic purposes can be grouped into two general categories according to the type of discursive strategy employed. The first of these consists in a consciousinflationof the concept of pragmatism in order to establish it as widely as possible within the disciplinary discourse of philosophy. The second consists in adeflationaryapplication of the concept, in order to distinguish it from the professional self-image of academic philosophy in a marked and even provocative way. What each variant has in
1
2
Introduction
common is its tendency to criticize as “representationalist” the debate between realism and antirealism. At the center of this debate, which has left its imprint on twentieth-century thought, lies the problem of whether our mental representations should be understood realistically, as pictures of some externally existing reality, or antirealistically, as constructions of that realm. For the deflationists, this debate is seen as a case of fruitless bickering around the quasi-religious question of a sublime, metaphysical reality that—whether from the outside or from the inside—is believed to determine the contours of our speech and thought. Instead of searching ever further for this ultimate authority or foundation, the deflationists recommend that we view our knowledge as a collection of tools for the democratically-oriented transformation of reality, for which we alone are responsible (Rorty). In contrast to this political and humanistic critique, the inflationists formulate their critique of the debate between finding and making from a logical and analytic perspective. Their response to representationalism is an antirepresentationalist epistemology whose foundations are developed in such frameworks as normative pragmatics (Brandom), undogmatic empiricism (McDowell), or interpretational theories of truth (Davidson). The contributions toThe Pragmatic Turn in Philosophyexplore how these various discursive strategies are related and what their pertinence is to the relationship between pragmatism and philosophy as a whole. Perhaps the primary importance of this collection, however, lies in its demonstration that, in light of the current reinvestment in pragmatic thinking, the fabled divisions between analytic and continental thought are being rapidly replaced by a transcontinental desire to work on common problems in a common idiom. Of course, much of the work of deconstructing the continental/ analytic divide remains to be undertaken, and imposing obstacles remain. Idiom and style, to mention two, would seem to transcend categorization as merely external or secondary differences. Analytic philosophers tend to dismiss continental philosophers as being too literary, tend to fault their lack of rigor, of clarity, of precision. Continental thinkers, in turn, often ridicule analytic philosophy for its pretensions to scientificity and spurn it as positivistic, dry, irrelevant. Richard Rorty once characterized, in his inimitable way, the difference between continental and analytic philosophy as being little more than the difference between those philosophers who thought what was important was to read the history of philosophy and those who thought what was important was to read the last ten years of journal articles; and, indeed, in American departments of philosophy those who pay attention to thinkers of the continental tradition are referred to more often than not as historians. What this volume puts forth is a potential ground for a meeting between these idioms, a common ground of concern and place for interaction. It is
Introduction
3
our conviction that the century from which we have emerged has born witness to a sea change in philosophy, irrespective of on which side of the divide one stands. Recognized as such or not, a pragmatic philosophy has gained ascendancy over the traditional concerns of a representationalist epistemology that has determined much of the intellectual and cultural life of modernity; we believe that the philosophy of the next century will emerge from this recognition, and that the practice of this emergence is well underway. Moreover, in the age of globalization, an ecumenical philosophy represents an important contribution to the task of bringing together the autonomous disciplines into a transdisciplinary network of knowledge practices; perhaps a reenergized pragmatism will provide the philosophical support for this project. In the first piece in this volume, “The Insistence on Futurity: Pragmatism’s Temporal Structure,” Ludwig Nagl focuses on the question of time and temporality that figures so centrally in the thought of William James. He begins by arguing that the pragmatist test of whether a theoretical question makes any practical difference does not primarily serve to abolish the big metaphysical questions, but rather serves to distinguish the concerns of a real and living humanity from the intellectualistic pseudoproblems of professional philosophy. James’s pragmatic reflections on temporality should be thought of in this way: as breaking through the appearances of speculative reason in order to create a space for “the Will to Believe.” Beyond physicalist ontologies and aprioristic intellectualizing, James stood for a temporalization of time whose realization would entail the opening up of a multiplicity of time-horizons. This becomes the basis for James to throw a pragmatically-selective light on old metaphysical controversies, such as those between materialism and spiritualism, or between free will and determinism. Nagl concludes by bringing James’s pragmatic logic of hope to bear on current discussions in the philosophy of religion, specifically in the work of the French political historian Marcel Gauchet. For Gauchet, we are living in a postreligious age in which hope for the future has become a meaningless openness to whatever comes, totally lacking the stabilizing force of a utopian ideal. Nagl counters this notion with James’s “insistence on futurity,” which in no way leads to the leveling out of the ever-receding other of the future, but rather makes visible the borders of the kind of humanistic “inner transcendence” so important to the thought of writers like Habermas, Rorty, and Gauchet himself. The pertinence of James to contemporary moral concerns continues to be at stake in Hilary Putnam’s contribution, “Philosophy as a Reconstructive Activity: William James on Moral Philosophy.” Putnam seeks to locate in the work of William James the basis for a pragmatic theory of morals that would try neither to assume a transcendental authoritative status nor to dissolve ethical questions into an empirical cultural anthropology. In an early
  • Univers Univers
  • Ebooks Ebooks
  • Livres audio Livres audio
  • Presse Presse
  • Podcasts Podcasts
  • BD BD
  • Documents Documents